• Starting today August 7th, 2024, in order to post in the Married Couples, Courting Couples, or Singles forums, you will not be allowed to post if you have your Marital status designated as private. Announcements will be made in the respective forums as well but please note that if yours is currently listed as Private, you will need to submit a ticket in the Support Area to have yours changed.

The Second Law fallacy

shernren

you are not reading this.
Feb 17, 2005
8,463
515
38
Shah Alam, Selangor
Visit site
✟33,881.00
Faith
Protestant
Marital Status
In Relationship
As I described at length in the OP, their understanding of entropy, disorder and the 2nd Law would force them to conclude that crystals, eddies in water flow and boulders on top of rock columns are all forbidden by the Law. But such things (and millions of similar things) do exist, therefore their understanding must be flawed.

Ahh. I went back and refreshed myself with the OP and I see what you're saying. Thing is:

1. Crystals are actually low-entropy objects, relative to their surroundings. If you recall the discussion with metherion and me, entropy is roughly a measure of how much information we have vs how much information it would take to fully describe the system. Now if I say "Here's a crystal of salt", I'm actually giving you a lot of information (namely that there is regular ordering of the constituent ions), so that the amount of "unknown information" decreases by comparison, and hence the entropy.

2. A boulder on top of a rock column is also actually a low-entropy arrangement. I think I floundered on this when I last interacted with the thread but having spent a few months on partition functions I'm much better now :p

Imagine a plain with a sharp rock column; then imagine plotting the probability density of "where a massive rock can be" on this plain. The rock's potential energy varies according to its height; this causes an energy to be associated with each possible spatial position, which then feeds into the probability density via Boltzmann factors.

Now if I'm simply looking at the distribution of "where the rock can be", I'll find that it could be anywhere on the plain, with a very small probability of being on the rock column. But if I limit myself to "where on the rock column can the rock be" I will find that I have suddenly specified the probability distribution very severely. And that's why a video of a rock jumping onto a rock column is surely taken backwards!

Thing is, the Second Law specifies that entropy must increase (given suitable constraints); but it never says how fast entropy must increase. So the rock will eventually fall, but it might take a million years to do so.

3. Eddies, convection cells, and the like are actually nonequilibrium states. (Note: even stationary states can be non-equilibrium states!) The very concept of entropy becomes rather useless.

What happens is that over a non-equilibrium process, the system behaves chaotically (in the formal senses of chaos theory), and its phase space portrait becomes fractalized. Now the entropy is the integral of p Log(p) over phase space, where p is the probability density. Imagine trying to do that integral over the Mandelbrot pattern, or over a block of swiss cheese: no matter how you draw up your boundaries, you hit regions of phase space where the density (after some time) becomes zero - but the log of zero can't be defined sensibly!

So in fact, two of your examples are actually low-entropy systems, and the third doesn't quite have an entropy measure.

In classical thermodynamics (I’m speaking of nonreacting systems here) one of the assumptions is that the number of particles and the temperature differential are both large enough that that’s not a factor. Wouldn’t the analogue for reacting systems be that if the difference between the critical energy and the available thermal energy is greater than Boltzman’s constant, the reaction is disfavored?

I don’t consider it snarky to assume that the other person is intelligent enough to follow a line of reasoning.

The snarkiness lies in the fact that the Fluctuation Theorems are not yet a part of common scientific parlance (among non-science people, at least) in the way that the SLoT and evolution are. It's therefore somewhat an argument from privilege.

I'm not sure what you mean by the "critical energy". The rule of thumb that I know of is that if the activation energy is less than 10 k_B T, a substantial amount of particles will be able to cross that activation barrier. (Whether or not the reaction then gets any further depends of course on the energetics of the whole reaction.)

Thing is, though, that assumes an equilibrium distribution of the reactants. But in small systems equilibrium is a precious commodity! Furthermore, living organisms are flagrantly not at thermodynamic equilibrium with their surroundings. This is (in my interpretation) principally because life consists of micromachinery which, because it is so small and so far from equilibrium, has a significant chance of decreasing local entropy.

For a good visual example of this sort of fluctuations, see videos of micromachinery such as this: YouTube - Microscopic cog occasionally the ratchet turns backwards, signifying a temporary decrease of entropy as the system reverts into a probabilistically-unlikely state.
 
  • Like
Reactions: chilehed
Upvote 0

Assyrian

Basically pulling an Obama (Thanks Calminian!)
Mar 31, 2006
14,868
991
Wales
✟42,286.00
Faith
Christian
Marital Status
Married
Ahh. I went back and refreshed myself with the OP and I see what you're saying. Thing is:

1. Crystals are actually low-entropy objects, relative to their surroundings. If you recall the discussion with metherion and me, entropy is roughly a measure of how much information we have vs how much information it would take to fully describe the system. Now if I say "Here's a crystal of salt", I'm actually giving you a lot of information (namely that there is regular ordering of the constituent ions), so that the amount of "unknown information" decreases by comparison, and hence the entropy.

2. A boulder on top of a rock column is also actually a low-entropy arrangement. I think I floundered on this when I last interacted with the thread but having spent a few months on partition functions I'm much better now :p

Imagine a plain with a sharp rock column; then imagine plotting the probability density of "where a massive rock can be" on this plain. The rock's potential energy varies according to its height; this causes an energy to be associated with each possible spatial position, which then feeds into the probability density via Boltzmann factors.

Now if I'm simply looking at the distribution of "where the rock can be", I'll find that it could be anywhere on the plain, with a very small probability of being on the rock column. But if I limit myself to "where on the rock column can the rock be" I will find that I have suddenly specified the probability distribution very severely. And that's why a video of a rock jumping onto a rock column is surely taken backwards!

Thing is, the Second Law specifies that entropy must increase (given suitable constraints); but it never says how fast entropy must increase. So the rock will eventually fall, but it might take a million years to do so.

3. Eddies, convection cells, and the like are actually nonequilibrium states. (Note: even stationary states can be non-equilibrium states!) The very concept of entropy becomes rather useless.

What happens is that over a non-equilibrium process, the system behaves chaotically (in the formal senses of chaos theory), and its phase space portrait becomes fractalized. Now the entropy is the integral of p Log(p) over phase space, where p is the probability density. Imagine trying to do that integral over the Mandelbrot pattern, or over a block of swiss cheese: no matter how you draw up your boundaries, you hit regions of phase space where the density (after some time) becomes zero - but the log of zero can't be defined sensibly!
I wouldn't have though it had to be. If the probability is 0, it means the particle or system isn't going to be in that state. It is outside the phase space, even if outside refers to a bubble. Meanwhile on your way to p=0 the integral of p Log(p) has long gone to 0 too. It is like trying to calculate the protein content in your block of swiss cheese, the holes may make you calculation more complicated, but you don't actually have to count the protein content of the holes.

On the question of open and closed system, I wonder if a parable could help.

Special Cyclists claim bicycle tyres must have been specially inflated by God. The proof is that bicycle tyres contradict Boyle's Law. Boyle's law states that for a fixed mass of gas at constant temperature, the pressure and volume are inversely proportional. You increase the pressure and the volume decreases. But with bicycle tyres and balloons when you increase the pressure the volume increases. It is God that giveth the increase 1Cor 3:7. Theistic Inflaters (and atheistic cyclists) often reply that this is rubbish, Boyle's Law is only applies to ideal gases. Having to pump up your bicycle tyre is hardly ideal. Yet for the Special Cyclist, when God created the heavens and the earth and everything in them, he said that it was very good, so the gas must be ideal. Or Theistic Inflaters can argue that it applies at constant temperature, whereas you can feel the bicycle pump getting hot (fires of hell the Special Cyclists reply). The argument gets a bit closer to the problem when T.I.s say that pressure and volume are only inversely proportional for a fixed mass of gas, bicycle tyres are an open system because the pump is adding more gas. No reply the special cyclists, if it was an open system the tyre would leak. Or more aptly, they reply that according to Johnny 'Bicycle' Safari, from Answers in Cyclists, who should know because he has a Ph.D. in Physical Chemistry, Boyle's law applies to open systems too. So pressure and volume must be inversely proportional. Of course it does, the problem is taking a description of Boyle's law in a closed system and trying to apply it to an open system.

I am not sure if this is a separate problem or another aspect of the problem in the parable. The SLoT is very complex physics and most people who have come across it have been given a very simplified from, or an illustration of the SLoT in terms of a common effect, that disorder tends to increase (or in the parable the volume of gas in a piston decreases with pressure). And they mistake the simplified description, in some circumstances, for a universal law that applies everywhere in every circumstance.
 
Upvote 0

shernren

you are not reading this.
Feb 17, 2005
8,463
515
38
Shah Alam, Selangor
Visit site
✟33,881.00
Faith
Protestant
Marital Status
In Relationship
I wouldn't have though it had to be. If the probability is 0, it means the particle or system isn't going to be in that state. It is outside the phase space, even if outside refers to a bubble. Meanwhile on your way to p=0 the integral of p Log(p) has long gone to 0 too. It is like trying to calculate the protein content in your block of swiss cheese, the holes may make you calculation more complicated, but you don't actually have to count the protein content of the holes.

You're right that as p tends to zero, p Log p does actually tend to zero instead of the ineffable negative infinity. I don't know why I never noticed that earlier. (But my lecturer said so, and he's really smart! Will an argument from authority suffice for now? :p )

On the question of open and closed system, I wonder if a parable could help.

Special Cyclists claim bicycle tyres must have been specially inflated by God. The proof is that bicycle tyres contradict Boyle's Law. Boyle's law states that for a fixed mass of gas at constant temperature, the pressure and volume are inversely proportional. You increase the pressure and the volume decreases. But with bicycle tyres and balloons when you increase the pressure the volume increases. It is God that giveth the increase 1Cor 3:7. Theistic Inflaters (and atheistic cyclists) often reply that this is rubbish, Boyle's Law is only applies to ideal gases. Having to pump up your bicycle tyre is hardly ideal. Yet for the Special Cyclist, when God created the heavens and the earth and everything in them, he said that it was very good, so the gas must be ideal. Or Theistic Inflaters can argue that it applies at constant temperature, whereas you can feel the bicycle pump getting hot (fires of hell the Special Cyclists reply). The argument gets a bit closer to the problem when T.I.s say that pressure and volume are only inversely proportional for a fixed mass of gas, bicycle tyres are an open system because the pump is adding more gas. No reply the special cyclists, if it was an open system the tyre would leak. Or more aptly, they reply that according to Johnny 'Bicycle' Safari, from Answers in Cyclists, who should know because he has a Ph.D. in Physical Chemistry, Boyle's law applies to open systems too. So pressure and volume must be inversely proportional. Of course it does, the problem is taking a description of Boyle's law in a closed system and trying to apply it to an open system.

I am not sure if this is a separate problem or another aspect of the problem in the parable. The SLoT is very complex physics and most people who have come across it have been given a very simplified from, or an illustration of the SLoT in terms of a common effect, that disorder tends to increase (or in the parable the volume of gas in a piston decreases with pressure). And they mistake the simplified description, in some circumstances, for a universal law that applies everywhere in every circumstance.

Hehe, it's a cute little parable.

The first problem (with the creationist argument - not your parable) is that they aren't being clear just what they're talking about. If they said that abiogenesis violated the SLoT, they might just have a shot at things. I haven't actually thought a lot about that situation yet, except to say that non-equilibrium chemistry is actually quite firmly known, if somewhat arcane - the Belousov-Zhabotinsky reaction is a fine example of a "cyclic" chemical reaction; the concentrations of the various reactants oscillate with a well-defined period (almost like the position of a pendulum), so that if one defines the up-swing as an increase in entropy, the concomitant down-swing must be a decrease in entropy!

Abiogenesis is then really a problem of unusually arcane non-equilibrium chemistry, a topic on which neither I nor Safarti has any experience (even though we both do / have done quite a bit of work in the general area of physical chemistry).

As an interlude, the SLoT really is about disorder in a general sense. In its most utterly fundamental statement, the SLoT is a simple consequence of the fact that causality respects probability. Interacting systems are driven into their most probable state; it is simply unfortunate that our cognitive circuits have evolved over the millenia to associate such most-probable-states with disorder. The genius of the SLoT is in recognizing that the state in which temperatures are equal is, in fact, the most probable state.

Thus, it really may not be too bad an analogy to say that the clutter in a room demonstrates the Second Law of Thermodynamics. In a sense, there are more immediate, proximate mechanisms that cause the disorder to build up; blaming it on the SLoT is a little like blaming it on quantum mechanics, like using a sledgehammer to pull out a tooth. But it is a good analogy in the sense that, say, the components of the immune system can be compared to the parts of an army: good homologous arguments.

The error is more subtle (and so is my thinking since two or three years ago when I first contributed to this thread). We'll compare two thought experiments. The first is a control, or placebo: it demonstrates normal thinking. Imagine a kitchen table and an egg. Because of gravity, the configurations in which the egg is on the table are far less likely than the configurations in which the egg is on the floor. Furthermore, again because of gravity (and the legendary frailty of egg shells) the configurations in which the egg is whole are again far less likely than the configurations in which the egg is cracked and messed up. As such, our intuition tells us that it's very likely for an egg to roll off the table, fall to the floor and smash; it is less likely but still thinkable for an egg to roll off the table, fall to the floor but not break; but it is quite ridiculous for the egg to be smashed on the floor, reconstitute itself into a whole egg, and then jump onto the table. Furthermore, the SLoT can (with a sufficient amount of tedium / funding / PhD slaves) be applied to the situation rigorously.

Now imagine loving parents having triplets. Unfortunately, though loving, they are not very responsible, and they end up being bitten by a radioactive spider while performing an experiment with gamma rays on a spaceship just before it gets hit by a solar flare. The ensuing genetic mutations affect all of their children. One child grows up with all sorts of enhancements like web glands and wall-crawling bristles; one child grows up with normal anatomy (though he occasionally turns green and strips naked when he's angry); and one child grows up with his internal organs deformed or absent altogether (although he gains the mystical ability to stretch himself and inexplicably stay alive).

Now our Spidey-boy's mutations are an example of what the creationists consider an increase in order, the addition of function via genetic change. Our poor old juvenile Reed Richard's mutations on the other hand are an example of what the creationists consider a decrease in order, the reduction of function via genetic change. Now
since the SLoT always causes order to decrease,

we should expect to see more Reed Richards than Peter Parkers,
and as generation after generation loses function, creatures should devolve, but they haven't, so if evolution explains today's biodiversity, it must violate the SLoT!

There are two errors in the creationist's argument, one of which is unique to the invocation of the SLoT, and one which is generic in all their arguments. You'll notice that their argument is predicated on Reeds being more common than Peters. The problem is in their invoking the SLoT to justify that. In our egg example, there is an energetic difference between an egg on table and an egg on floor. Boltzmann factors (and the assumption of thermal equilibrium) allow us to convert those energetic differences into probabilities, and the SLoT then unassumingly predicts that the more likely state is, well, more likely.

But what, precisely, are the energetics of giving birth to a Reed instead of a Peter? Does it actually take more energy to give birth to a slightly more "ordered" (whatever that might mean) offspring? What are the thermodynamics of an Australopithecus having young with a slightly larger cranium than a slightly smaller cranium? Can I make a perpetual motion machine out of a reptile whose young have feathers instead of scales? Clearly not, but I could certainly make a perpetual motion machine out of eggs that spontaneously jump onto tables without external energy input.

So the first error is using the SLoT to assign those probability distributions. The reasoning creationist will, in response, drop the SLoT. "Okay, so apart from abiogenesis where chemicals really do need energy to react," (hence my earlier caveat), "mutations don't have thermodynamic probability distributions. But surely they still do have some probability distribution! And harmful mutations simply are more likely than beneficial mutations, even if that's not justified by the SLoT - it's just common sense!"

You see, the argument has stripped down and revealed that it was simply the "beneficial mutations are less likely" argument hiding behind a chemist's lab coat. And now all the usual evolutionist replies apply - beneficial mutations only need to happen once, the retention of beneficial mutations is far more likely than the retention of harmful mutations, neutral mutations can be exapted, as can spandrels and vestiges, etc. etc. ad infinitum ad nauseam.
 
Upvote 0

SkyWriting

The Librarian
Site Supporter
Jan 10, 2010
37,281
8,501
Milwaukee
✟411,038.00
Country
United States
Gender
Male
Faith
Non-Denom
Marital Status
Married
Politics
US-Others
It's obvious that you didn't bother to actually study what I wrote. What makes it REALLY obvious is that this link in particular affirms my position: it's correct to say that entropy is a measure of disorder only for a specific and limited definition of disorder.

But since you don't seem inclined to really think about what you read then there's no point in my discussing this any further with you.

Intelligent, useful, functional order. The opposite of a repeating pattern of marbles in ones head or a block of salt.
 
Upvote 0

Assyrian

Basically pulling an Obama (Thanks Calminian!)
Mar 31, 2006
14,868
991
Wales
✟42,286.00
Faith
Christian
Marital Status
Married
You're right that as p tends to zero, p Log p does actually tend to zero instead of the ineffable negative infinity. I don't know why I never noticed that earlier. (But my lecturer said so, and he's really smart! Will an argument from authority suffice for now? :p )
:bow:

Hehe, it's a cute little parable.

The first problem (with the creationist argument - not your parable) is that they aren't being clear just what they're talking about. If they said that abiogenesis violated the SLoT, they might just have a shot at things. I haven't actually thought a lot about that situation yet, except to say that non-equilibrium chemistry is actually quite firmly known, if somewhat arcane - the Belousov-Zhabotinsky reaction is a fine example of a "cyclic" chemical reaction; the concentrations of the various reactants oscillate with a well-defined period (almost like the position of a pendulum), so that if one defines the up-swing as an increase in entropy, the concomitant down-swing must be a decrease in entropy!

Abiogenesis is then really a problem of unusually arcane non-equilibrium chemistry, a topic on which neither I nor Safarti has any experience (even though we both do / have done quite a bit of work in the general area of physical chemistry).

As an interlude, the SLoT really is about disorder in a general sense. In its most utterly fundamental statement, the SLoT is a simple consequence of the fact that causality respects probability. Interacting systems are driven into their most probable state; it is simply unfortunate that our cognitive circuits have evolved over the millenia to associate such most-probable-states with disorder. The genius of the SLoT is in recognizing that the state in which temperatures are equal is, in fact, the most probable state.

Thus, it really may not be too bad an analogy to say that the clutter in a room demonstrates the Second Law of Thermodynamics. In a sense, there are more immediate, proximate mechanisms that cause the disorder to build up; blaming it on the SLoT is a little like blaming it on quantum mechanics, like using a sledgehammer to pull out a tooth. But it is a good analogy in the sense that, say, the components of the immune system can be compared to the parts of an army: good homologous arguments.

The error is more subtle (and so is my thinking since two or three years ago when I first contributed to this thread). We'll compare two thought experiments. The first is a control, or placebo: it demonstrates normal thinking. Imagine a kitchen table and an egg. Because of gravity, the configurations in which the egg is on the table are far less likely than the configurations in which the egg is on the floor. Furthermore, again because of gravity (and the legendary frailty of egg shells) the configurations in which the egg is whole are again far less likely than the configurations in which the egg is cracked and messed up. As such, our intuition tells us that it's very likely for an egg to roll off the table, fall to the floor and smash; it is less likely but still thinkable for an egg to roll off the table, fall to the floor but not break; but it is quite ridiculous for the egg to be smashed on the floor, reconstitute itself into a whole egg, and then jump onto the table. Furthermore, the SLoT can (with a sufficient amount of tedium / funding / PhD slaves) be applied to the situation rigorously.

Now imagine loving parents having triplets. Unfortunately, though loving, they are not very responsible, and they end up being bitten by a radioactive spider while performing an experiment with gamma rays on a spaceship just before it gets hit by a solar flare. The ensuing genetic mutations affect all of their children. One child grows up with all sorts of enhancements like web glands and wall-crawling bristles; one child grows up with normal anatomy (though he occasionally turns green and strips naked when he's angry); and one child grows up with his internal organs deformed or absent altogether (although he gains the mystical ability to stretch himself and inexplicably stay alive).

Now our Spidey-boy's mutations are an example of what the creationists consider an increase in order, the addition of function via genetic change. Our poor old juvenile Reed Richard's mutations on the other hand are an example of what the creationists consider a decrease in order, the reduction of function via genetic change. Now
since the SLoT always causes order to decrease,

we should expect to see more Reed Richards than Peter Parkers,
and as generation after generation loses function, creatures should devolve, but they haven't, so if evolution explains today's biodiversity, it must violate the SLoT!

There are two errors in the creationist's argument, one of which is unique to the invocation of the SLoT, and one which is generic in all their arguments. You'll notice that their argument is predicated on Reeds being more common than Peters. The problem is in their invoking the SLoT to justify that. In our egg example, there is an energetic difference between an egg on table and an egg on floor. Boltzmann factors (and the assumption of thermal equilibrium) allow us to convert those energetic differences into probabilities, and the SLoT then unassumingly predicts that the more likely state is, well, more likely.

But what, precisely, are the energetics of giving birth to a Reed instead of a Peter? Does it actually take more energy to give birth to a slightly more "ordered" (whatever that might mean) offspring? What are the thermodynamics of an Australopithecus having young with a slightly larger cranium than a slightly smaller cranium? Can I make a perpetual motion machine out of a reptile whose young have feathers instead of scales? Clearly not, but I could certainly make a perpetual motion machine out of eggs that spontaneously jump onto tables without external energy input.
The more I hear about the SLoT the more eerily it sound like quantum mechanics and an answer to the question of why quantum mechanics isn't seen operating on a macro level. I had been thinking of the teenager blaming the state of his room on the SLoT, or even refusing to tidy because he didn't want to disobey the law. But this raises another even more disturbing possibility, the the room wasn't actually untidy until his mother observed it.

So the first error is using the SLoT to assign those probability distributions. The reasoning creationist will, in response, drop the SLoT. "Okay, so apart from abiogenesis where chemicals really do need energy to react," (hence my earlier caveat), "mutations don't have thermodynamic probability distributions. But surely they still do have some probability distribution! And harmful mutations simply are more likely than beneficial mutations, even if that's not justified by the SLoT - it's just common sense!"

You see, the argument has stripped down and revealed that it was simply the "beneficial mutations are less likely" argument hiding behind a chemist's lab coat. And now all the usual evolutionist replies apply - beneficial mutations only need to happen once, the retention of beneficial mutations is far more likely than the retention of harmful mutations, neutral mutations can be exapted, as can spandrels and vestiges, etc. etc. ad infinitum ad nauseam.
Maxwell's demon?
 
Upvote 0

chilehed

Veteran
Jul 31, 2003
4,735
1,399
64
Michigan
✟250,727.00
Faith
Catholic
Marital Status
Married
shernren said:
Ahh. I went back and refreshed myself with the OP and I see what you're saying. Thing is:

1. Crystals are actually low-entropy objects, relative to their surroundings. If you recall the discussion with metherion and me, entropy is roughly a measure of how much information we have vs how much information it would take to fully describe the system. Now if I say "Here's a crystal of salt", I'm actually giving you a lot of information (namely that there is regular ordering of the constituent ions), so that the amount of "unknown information" decreases by comparison, and hence the entropy.
I’m not sure that you’re keeping in mind the specific error I was addressing in that section of the OP: the flawed definition of order.

Also, I think that you’re failing to maintain the necessary category distinctions. The question isn’t whether or not the boulder on the pillar is in a different entropy state than the one on the ground, it’s whether or not the boulder being on the pillar constitutes a violation of the law. It most certainly doesn’t, because any real process that results in that state complies with the Law (in fact, the work done in lifting the boulder from the ground to the height of the pillar is entirely reversible).

The same holds true for any of the processes that result in eddies and the like: all of them comply with the Law. I don’t understand how anyone can think that the concept of entropy is useless in such states, because every process by definition transitions through nonequilibrium states and we know that all real processes comply with the Second Law. That’s why we know that a process that violates the Law is not a real process.

shernren said:
2. A boulder on top of a rock column is also actually a low-entropy arrangement…
Low entropy compared to what? Compared to the state that existed before it got exposed through weathering? Be careful: if you redefine the ground state in the middle of the analysis then it’s easy to fool yourself into thinking that the Law’s been violated.

Or compared to the state that existed before you lifted it up and put it there? I think not…do the 2nd Law analysis. You remove heat from a reservoir (which lowers the entropy of the reservoir) and use it to lift the rock (which increases the entropy of the rock). The total entropy generated is zero, and it’s the total entropy generated which is the subject of the Law.

shernren said:
chilehed said:
In classical thermodynamics (I’m speaking of nonreacting systems here) one of the assumptions is that the number of particles and the temperature differential are both large enough that that’s not a factor. Wouldn’t the analogue for reacting systems be that if the difference between the critical energy and the available thermal energy is greater than Boltzman’s constant, the reaction is disfavored?
I'm not sure what you mean by the "critical energy". The rule of thumb that I know of is that if the activation energy is less than 10 k_B T, a substantial amount of particles will be able to cross that activation barrier. (Whether or not the reaction then gets any further depends of course on the energetics of the whole reaction.)
Critical energy and threshold energy are other names for activation energy. Perhaps they are less used today than in the past.

Again, my background isn’t in chemistry, and I’m not familiar with the unit k_B T. But it sounds like the answer to my question is yes, at least qualitatively.

I’ve gotten really busy at work and at home, and so my posting frequency will suffer. That’s in addition to the fact that I try to think very carefully about my replies on this topic; it can take a while to develop precision in my thoughts and words and I’m still not as successful as I’d like.

Remember, all thermodynamic properties (including entropy) are properties of the macrostate as the macrostate has been defined. It’s not a property of any one of the resulting possible microstates; all of those microstates by definition have the same entropy, including the ones that are highly improbable. You might be interested in a paper I found about the Gibbs Paradox: http://bayes.wustl.edu/etj/articles/gibbs.paradox.pdf
 
Upvote 0