By example, an action must take place that convinces you. Not just words, but an experience for you.So how can a non-believer ascertain the truth if such claims are inaccessible?
Upvote
0
Starting today August 7th, 2024, in order to post in the Married Couples, Courting Couples, or Singles forums, you will not be allowed to post if you have your Marital status designated as private. Announcements will be made in the respective forums as well but please note that if yours is currently listed as Private, you will need to submit a ticket in the Support Area to have yours changed.
By example, an action must take place that convinces you. Not just words, but an experience for you.So how can a non-believer ascertain the truth if such claims are inaccessible?
Well obviously one has to be convinced before accepting a proposition but that doesn't really answer my main question in this thread. For instance, how do you know that what you experienced actually tracks reality? One "knows" that a pencil's ends are flapping when holding it from one end and moving it up and down, just by looking at it. Of course we now know this is an optical illusion. We "know" that pink exists because we perceive it. Except now we recognize that it's not part of the color spectrum and therefore not "out there" somewhere but simply our brain creating that inner first-person experience by taking the two outermost colors and fusing them together. We "know" that if we have some ailment and take a remedy that hasn't been rigorously tested by merely touted as effective by word of mouth, it must be the case that our ailment's treatment was caused by it if A came before B. But that's a fallacy of correlation implying causality. And on and on. So my question remains: how do these traditional causes of belief work around our cognitive errors?By example, an action must take place that convinces you. Not just words, but an experience for you.
Well obviously one has to be convinced before accepting a proposition but that doesn't really answer my main question in this thread. For instance, how do you know that what you experienced actually tracks reality? One "knows" that a pencil's ends are flapping when holding it from one end and moving it up and down, just by looking at it. Of course we now know this is an optical illusion. We "know" that pink exists because we perceive it. Except now we recognize that it's not part of the color spectrum and therefore not "out there" somewhere but simply our brain creating that inner first-person experience by taking the two outermost colors and fusing them together. We "know" that if we have some ailment and take a remedy that hasn't been rigorously tested by merely touted as effective by word of mouth, it must be the case that our ailment's treatment was caused by it if A came before B. But that's a fallacy of correlation implying causality. And on and on. So my question remains: how do these traditional causes of belief work around our cognitive errors?
I don't think you will find an answer because it seems nothing is real to you because you constantly question without reason. We probably are not even speaking right now.Well obviously one has to be convinced before accepting a proposition but that doesn't really answer my main question in this thread. For instance, how do you know that what you experienced actually tracks reality? One "knows" that a pencil's ends are flapping when holding it from one end and moving it up and down, just by looking at it. Of course we now know this is an optical illusion. We "know" that pink exists because we perceive it. Except now we recognize that it's not part of the color spectrum and therefore not "out there" somewhere but simply our brain creating that inner first-person experience by taking the two outermost colors and fusing them together. We "know" that if we have some ailment and take a remedy that hasn't been rigorously tested by merely touted as effective by word of mouth, it must be the case that our ailment's treatment was caused by it if A came before B. But that's a fallacy of correlation implying causality. And on and on. So my question remains: how do these traditional causes of belief work around our cognitive errors?
Nothing is real to me? When did I say that? I think many things are real, in fact.I don't think you will find an answer because it seems nothing is real to you because you constantly question without reason. We probably are not even speaking right now.
I didn't mean to offend. SorryNothing is real to me? When did I say that? I think many things are real, in fact.
Of course I question everything. Why shouldn't I given our cognitive errors? Should I just acquiesce to claims just because? How is that questioning "without reason" exactly?
Your response is nothing more than a straw man argument. You are no longer addressing any of my points but simply painting my argument as some ridiculous reduction and attacking that false construction. And here I thought we were heading somewhere.
That doesn't answer the question. There are better ways to acquire knowledge than others. Blinding trusting authority is worse than skeptical inquiry and repeated testing, for instance.
How do you know the miracle is an actual miracle as opposed to a cheap trick? And how do you know that the miracles of the Bible are true? After all, they are assertions written in a book. The fact that they weren't written down by eyewitnesses is the least of the problems.
Are you sure you are using the correct definition of faith?
Heb 11:1 Now faith is the substance of things hoped for, the evidence of things unseen.
Sounds like Faith is evidence of God by experience of God and that is why it is a gift from God and not something we generate ourselves.
Once our belief is corroborated by substance and evidence, then it is no longer just what we think to be true. We know it to be true without a shadow of a doubt.
The physical sciences rely more upon our senses than religion does, so, if our senses are as unreliable as you say they are, the sciences are in big trouble, aren't they?
Not really. Science relies on empirical evidence, which many many scientists observe and is external to the senses.
With religious beliefs, there is no such external evidence that can be seen and acknowledged by all.
Not really. Science relies on empirical evidence, which many many scientists observe and is external to the senses.
With religious beliefs, there is no such external evidence that can be seen and acknowledged by all.
Could very well be true, but that really wasn't what I was addressing to the poster I was responding to.
How do you propose to divorce empiricism from use of the senses - sight especially?
When 1,000 scientists get the same results from experiments and observe through visual means the same thing and have empirical evidence to support it, tough to toss that out as not reliable.
Theology, in its methodology, cannot be tripped up by supposed limitations in our sensory apparatus, because it doesn't rely upon them.
When 1,000 scientists get the same results from experiments and observe through visual means the same thing and have empirical evidence to support it, tough to toss that out as not reliable.
What methodology does theology rely on? What is a standard to test the methodology for accuracy?
That presupposes that our senses have evolved to give us true information about our environment, as opposed to giving us a picture good enough to ensure our survival long enough to reproduce.
The Bible is, for Christian theology, the source of raw data, which a theologian then goes to work on. The said theologian is subject to a similar kind of peer review process as a scientist. If his colleagues think that his ideas have veered too far away from what can be justified, he is unlikely to find his paper being published in the Harvard Theological Review.
What methodology does theology rely on? What is a standard to test the methodology for accuracy?