E
EgonTowst
Guest
Wanted to share an article/blog post I wrote elsewhere. Haven't gotten any feedback yet, and thought it might stir some interesting conversation here. Remember this is a blog post I wrote for another website, particularly a Reformed website, and a Reformed website that has a layman audience base, so if I sound like I'm "talking at" non-Calvinists at times, my apologies. I do not wish to unkind, and hope nothing in this post will come across as such. I'm just trying to encourage some fruitful discussion on my thoughts.
I will have to split this into two posts, because it is too long for one.
__________________________________________________________
The concept of “free will” is so frequently taken for granted that most today would not even think to question it. However, I would suggest this is because few take the time to examine what they actually mean by it. I want to spend a few moments discussing different ways in which “free will” can be defined. Through an analysis of these possible definitions, I will argue that there is no way to coherently define a realistic concept of “free will” in humanity. Christians believe this tradition because they take the concept for granted (it being the common assumption among most everyone else around them) without seriously examining and challenging what they assume to be true.
It is not my intention to present a biblical argument against “free will” here. That I will do elsewhere, as Scripture is my real basis for arguing that man's will is enslaved. Rather, here my primary intention is to examine the concept of “free will,” and possible ways in which to define the term, in order to simply demonstrate that those who use such terminology are not being very coherent or consistent in doing so. So before anyone criticizes me for “relying on philosophy instead of Scripture to argue my Calvinism,” no, I am not presenting a positive case for Calvinism. I am questioning the consistency of those who argue against Calvinism. My positive case for my position will come in later posts.
In order to avoid the tremendous amount of confusion that so often colors the Calvinism debate, we have to define our terms. “Free will” is a philosophical term, not a biblical term, so it must be defined by those who wish to use such language. Further, “free will” cannot be defined in a way that makes it synonymous to the mere act of choosing, because the debate on “free will” involves questions concerning the nature of man's choices, not the reality of them. Yet, the arguments of many “free will” proponents seem to ignore this (or perhaps they’re just not aware of it). The typical strategy involves little more than referencing Scripture verses that refer to the fact that men choose Christ, as if that is somehow supposed to settle something. This equivocation inevitably results in a failure to recognize what those who oppose “free will” are actually arguing, which in itself unfortunately accounts for a vast majority of the debates that take place.
Dave Hunt, for instance, argues from page 169 and following in his book What Love is This? that the Calvinist view implies that God “causes” people to do things as if they were “cardboard puppets.” In a [link]radio broadcast in 2010 by Chuck Smith and Bryan Brodersen of Calvary Chapel, the statement was made that Calvinists believe God “makes it impossible for people to come to Him” (5:15ff minute mark). In another [link]radio broadcast (date unknown), one individual makes the claim that Calvinists believe “man does not have a will” (6:44ff minute mark). Also of Calvary Chapel, George Bryson has likened Calvinism to fatalism in his book The Dark Side of Calvinism, page 21. Norman Geisler accuses the Calvinist position on page 47 of Chosen but Free of suggesting that God “force[s people] into His kingdom against their wills.” Every one of these accusations (and there are many more like them) is so far off the mark it is embarrassing. Not one of these men, or the many like them, has apparently ever taken the time to seriously study and seek to understand the view they oppose before hastily trying to find ways to dismiss it. This is dishonest scholarship, and yet it is representative of the kind of argumentation we hear coming from the vast majority of non-Calvinists.
I'd like to offer a proposal. I suggest that there are essentially two ways in which “free will” can be broadly defined. One of these ways will prove to be unrealistic upon examination, and is therefore easily objectionable. The other way is no real definition of “free will” at all, because it simply involves equating the concept of “free​ will” with what it means to simply ​have​ a will (this is the error of equivocation that many such as those just mentioned are making). I suggest that this is no definition of “free will” at all because ​no one​ would object to the fact that we ​have​ a will, and yet there are people who object to the idea that our will is ​free​. Thus, any coherent definition of the concept must articulate a distinction between what it means to ​have​ a will and what it means for the will to be ​free​. However, this, as I will show, will leave us only with the option of defining “free will” in such a way that the concept must simply be dismissed as nonsense. So my proposal is that we should do away with “free will” terminology altogether. Either it causes confusion by postulating an incoherent concept, or it describes a view of humanity that anyone should be able to agree is unrealistic.
So what are these definitions? We can describe the actions of the will as either being “uncaused” or “caused.” I suggest that any definition of the nature of choice must fall into one of these categories. Let’s examine the definitions carefully.
1) The human will is uncaused in its operation. While it may be influenced by internal or external factors, these factors do not necessarily have to impact the decision that is made.
2) The human will is caused in its operation. While the will still operates legitimately (that is to say, men do make their own choices), there are always internal and/or external factors in play that will inevitably not only impact the decision making process, but necessarily determine the outcome.
I don’t see another way of defining the will. Either the will is (A) unaffected by internal and external factors, in which case it is uncaused, (B) potentially influenced by internal and external factors but not necessarily determined by them, in which case we can also say the will is uncaused (or at least can be), or (C) determined by internal and external factors, in which case the will is caused.
Further, note that both of these definitions acknowledge the fact that man has a will. Neither view denies the fact that men make their own choices. The second definition (that the will is caused) does not imply that a man unconsciously goes about doing things like a puppet being pulled on strings. That is not the sense in which I am using the term “caused” here. By “caused,” what I mean is that every action of the will is causally related to the factors that influence our decision making – meaning, simply, that while they are indeed our choices, every one of those choices has a specific reason that motivated it. The choice is causally related to its influencing factors because it cannot be separated from that reason. Rather than being made in a vacuum, the choice is a necessary response or reflection of the impact that one or more internal or external factors (such as desire, emotion, environment, logical inference, etc.) has on the will.
Now, the superficiality of the non-Calvinist position is quickly revealed when the average non-Calvinist is asked to define what he or she means by “free will.” Most often, neither of the above options will be provided as a definition, at least initially. Usually, the only definition that will be offered is something along the lines of, “‘free will’ means that we have the ability to choose.” But as I’ve already noted, this is not an answer to the question at all, because every view of the will, including those views which argue against “free will,” acknowledge that we have the ability to choose. The question does not concern whether that ability is present. The question concerns the nature of the ability. So, even when non-Calvinists believe they have defined “free will,” most often they have not. They assume a definition in their arguments, but they have not critically analyzed their thought deeply enough to articulate specifically what it is they are actually assuming. This is problematic as it hinders the non-Calvinist from being able to test and examine the validity of what he believes to be true, which should naturally raise suspicions concerning the role that unchecked tradition plays in determining one’s beliefs.
But we must examine these things. We can describe the will as either uncaused or caused. When asked in this way (“is the will uncaused or caused?”
, the non-Calvinist will almost invariably answer the former – “the will is uncaused.” But I suggest no one actually believes this to be the case. The language is attractive, which is why people will say they believe it to be true. However, upon careful examination the idea quickly becomes unfeasible.
As mentioned earlier, there are two ways in which we can describe a will that is “uncaused.” We can either say that our choices are unaffected by internal and external factors, or that internal and external factors (such as desires, emotions, logical inferences, etc.) have the potential to influence our decisions, but are not guaranteed to determine the outcomes. On these views, choices may or may not be impacted by underlying motives, but ultimately in either case it is not necessary that those motives always and inevitably determine the outcome. The problem with this view is that it implies that decision making, at least in theory, can occur in a vacuum. That is, even given all these potential influences, one can still make a choice that ultimately was not directly impacted or motivated by anything outside itself. It simply happened, and there was no “reason” that caused it to happen. If this is the theory free-willists hold to, they face insurmountable problems.
For one, there is no way to distinguish the act of willing, on this view, from an act of random chance. This destroys all grounds for reliability in an individual's choices. The reason we believe we can trust people, the reason we feel we can know what kind of decision a person is likely to make, is because we assume that an individual's character traits are necessarily going to impact their decision making. This assumes that choices are causally made. If it were possible for an individual to truly make choices that are uncaused, there would necessarily be no way to even begin to predict a person's choices. A person would have absolutely no grounds for rationally believing that the next time he encounters his best friend, he will not arbitrarily pull out a knife and stab him to death. The very fact that we trust people and believe we can predict the choices (or range of choices) of others indicates that on a subconscious level we recognize and presuppose that all our decisions are necessarily impacted by underlying factors. This is simply another way of saying that our choices are causally related to the factors that influence them.
Further, choices can have no meaning if they are uncaused. One of the fascinating ironies of criticisms that are leveled against Calvinism is that they can often be turned right around on the non-Calvinist on an even more legitimate basis. One such example is when non-Calvinists suggest that a man’s decision to love Christ is not a “real” and meaningful decision unless it is made “freely.” But the irony here is that meaning is based in causation, not freedom! The very language of “meaning” presupposes purpose, and the very language of “purpose” presupposes determination. If an individual made a completely arbitrary choice to choose Christ, then it was meaningless. It had no motive. It was just a random, thoughtless act. Of course, every non-Calvinist would say that those who choose Christ certainly have motive for doing so. They want to choose Him, for instance. But as soon as one confesses that this is so, they admit that choices are caused, not uncaused. A choice that is based on a particular motive or reason is a choice that is born out of a causal influence. There were underlying factors that caused the individual to choose the way he did.
There is another ironic implication of the idea that our choices are uncaused. Again, the non-Calvinist will often assert that in order for an individual to legitimately be held responsible for his choices, those choices must be “free.” But just as meaning is grounded in causation, so is responsibility. If an individual's choosing is not necessarily causally related to any character trait or other underlying influence, we cannot legitimately call it “his” choice. A random, purposeless, uncaused act, with no meaning or motive necessarily underlying it, cannot even be called a “choice” of the individual. If a man murders his friend and one were to suggest that his choices were uncaused, we would lose all grounds for accusing the culprit of being responsible for the murder. Yet if we admit that it was his choice, then we further evidence our conviction that the choice was determined by underlying motives, character traits, and/or other factors. It is, in fact, the recognition of underlying motive that causes us to say a criminal is guilty for his actions.
...
I will have to split this into two posts, because it is too long for one.
__________________________________________________________
The concept of “free will” is so frequently taken for granted that most today would not even think to question it. However, I would suggest this is because few take the time to examine what they actually mean by it. I want to spend a few moments discussing different ways in which “free will” can be defined. Through an analysis of these possible definitions, I will argue that there is no way to coherently define a realistic concept of “free will” in humanity. Christians believe this tradition because they take the concept for granted (it being the common assumption among most everyone else around them) without seriously examining and challenging what they assume to be true.
It is not my intention to present a biblical argument against “free will” here. That I will do elsewhere, as Scripture is my real basis for arguing that man's will is enslaved. Rather, here my primary intention is to examine the concept of “free will,” and possible ways in which to define the term, in order to simply demonstrate that those who use such terminology are not being very coherent or consistent in doing so. So before anyone criticizes me for “relying on philosophy instead of Scripture to argue my Calvinism,” no, I am not presenting a positive case for Calvinism. I am questioning the consistency of those who argue against Calvinism. My positive case for my position will come in later posts.
In order to avoid the tremendous amount of confusion that so often colors the Calvinism debate, we have to define our terms. “Free will” is a philosophical term, not a biblical term, so it must be defined by those who wish to use such language. Further, “free will” cannot be defined in a way that makes it synonymous to the mere act of choosing, because the debate on “free will” involves questions concerning the nature of man's choices, not the reality of them. Yet, the arguments of many “free will” proponents seem to ignore this (or perhaps they’re just not aware of it). The typical strategy involves little more than referencing Scripture verses that refer to the fact that men choose Christ, as if that is somehow supposed to settle something. This equivocation inevitably results in a failure to recognize what those who oppose “free will” are actually arguing, which in itself unfortunately accounts for a vast majority of the debates that take place.
Dave Hunt, for instance, argues from page 169 and following in his book What Love is This? that the Calvinist view implies that God “causes” people to do things as if they were “cardboard puppets.” In a [link]radio broadcast in 2010 by Chuck Smith and Bryan Brodersen of Calvary Chapel, the statement was made that Calvinists believe God “makes it impossible for people to come to Him” (5:15ff minute mark). In another [link]radio broadcast (date unknown), one individual makes the claim that Calvinists believe “man does not have a will” (6:44ff minute mark). Also of Calvary Chapel, George Bryson has likened Calvinism to fatalism in his book The Dark Side of Calvinism, page 21. Norman Geisler accuses the Calvinist position on page 47 of Chosen but Free of suggesting that God “force[s people] into His kingdom against their wills.” Every one of these accusations (and there are many more like them) is so far off the mark it is embarrassing. Not one of these men, or the many like them, has apparently ever taken the time to seriously study and seek to understand the view they oppose before hastily trying to find ways to dismiss it. This is dishonest scholarship, and yet it is representative of the kind of argumentation we hear coming from the vast majority of non-Calvinists.
I'd like to offer a proposal. I suggest that there are essentially two ways in which “free will” can be broadly defined. One of these ways will prove to be unrealistic upon examination, and is therefore easily objectionable. The other way is no real definition of “free will” at all, because it simply involves equating the concept of “free​ will” with what it means to simply ​have​ a will (this is the error of equivocation that many such as those just mentioned are making). I suggest that this is no definition of “free will” at all because ​no one​ would object to the fact that we ​have​ a will, and yet there are people who object to the idea that our will is ​free​. Thus, any coherent definition of the concept must articulate a distinction between what it means to ​have​ a will and what it means for the will to be ​free​. However, this, as I will show, will leave us only with the option of defining “free will” in such a way that the concept must simply be dismissed as nonsense. So my proposal is that we should do away with “free will” terminology altogether. Either it causes confusion by postulating an incoherent concept, or it describes a view of humanity that anyone should be able to agree is unrealistic.
So what are these definitions? We can describe the actions of the will as either being “uncaused” or “caused.” I suggest that any definition of the nature of choice must fall into one of these categories. Let’s examine the definitions carefully.
1) The human will is uncaused in its operation. While it may be influenced by internal or external factors, these factors do not necessarily have to impact the decision that is made.
2) The human will is caused in its operation. While the will still operates legitimately (that is to say, men do make their own choices), there are always internal and/or external factors in play that will inevitably not only impact the decision making process, but necessarily determine the outcome.
I don’t see another way of defining the will. Either the will is (A) unaffected by internal and external factors, in which case it is uncaused, (B) potentially influenced by internal and external factors but not necessarily determined by them, in which case we can also say the will is uncaused (or at least can be), or (C) determined by internal and external factors, in which case the will is caused.
Further, note that both of these definitions acknowledge the fact that man has a will. Neither view denies the fact that men make their own choices. The second definition (that the will is caused) does not imply that a man unconsciously goes about doing things like a puppet being pulled on strings. That is not the sense in which I am using the term “caused” here. By “caused,” what I mean is that every action of the will is causally related to the factors that influence our decision making – meaning, simply, that while they are indeed our choices, every one of those choices has a specific reason that motivated it. The choice is causally related to its influencing factors because it cannot be separated from that reason. Rather than being made in a vacuum, the choice is a necessary response or reflection of the impact that one or more internal or external factors (such as desire, emotion, environment, logical inference, etc.) has on the will.
Now, the superficiality of the non-Calvinist position is quickly revealed when the average non-Calvinist is asked to define what he or she means by “free will.” Most often, neither of the above options will be provided as a definition, at least initially. Usually, the only definition that will be offered is something along the lines of, “‘free will’ means that we have the ability to choose.” But as I’ve already noted, this is not an answer to the question at all, because every view of the will, including those views which argue against “free will,” acknowledge that we have the ability to choose. The question does not concern whether that ability is present. The question concerns the nature of the ability. So, even when non-Calvinists believe they have defined “free will,” most often they have not. They assume a definition in their arguments, but they have not critically analyzed their thought deeply enough to articulate specifically what it is they are actually assuming. This is problematic as it hinders the non-Calvinist from being able to test and examine the validity of what he believes to be true, which should naturally raise suspicions concerning the role that unchecked tradition plays in determining one’s beliefs.
But we must examine these things. We can describe the will as either uncaused or caused. When asked in this way (“is the will uncaused or caused?”
As mentioned earlier, there are two ways in which we can describe a will that is “uncaused.” We can either say that our choices are unaffected by internal and external factors, or that internal and external factors (such as desires, emotions, logical inferences, etc.) have the potential to influence our decisions, but are not guaranteed to determine the outcomes. On these views, choices may or may not be impacted by underlying motives, but ultimately in either case it is not necessary that those motives always and inevitably determine the outcome. The problem with this view is that it implies that decision making, at least in theory, can occur in a vacuum. That is, even given all these potential influences, one can still make a choice that ultimately was not directly impacted or motivated by anything outside itself. It simply happened, and there was no “reason” that caused it to happen. If this is the theory free-willists hold to, they face insurmountable problems.
For one, there is no way to distinguish the act of willing, on this view, from an act of random chance. This destroys all grounds for reliability in an individual's choices. The reason we believe we can trust people, the reason we feel we can know what kind of decision a person is likely to make, is because we assume that an individual's character traits are necessarily going to impact their decision making. This assumes that choices are causally made. If it were possible for an individual to truly make choices that are uncaused, there would necessarily be no way to even begin to predict a person's choices. A person would have absolutely no grounds for rationally believing that the next time he encounters his best friend, he will not arbitrarily pull out a knife and stab him to death. The very fact that we trust people and believe we can predict the choices (or range of choices) of others indicates that on a subconscious level we recognize and presuppose that all our decisions are necessarily impacted by underlying factors. This is simply another way of saying that our choices are causally related to the factors that influence them.
Further, choices can have no meaning if they are uncaused. One of the fascinating ironies of criticisms that are leveled against Calvinism is that they can often be turned right around on the non-Calvinist on an even more legitimate basis. One such example is when non-Calvinists suggest that a man’s decision to love Christ is not a “real” and meaningful decision unless it is made “freely.” But the irony here is that meaning is based in causation, not freedom! The very language of “meaning” presupposes purpose, and the very language of “purpose” presupposes determination. If an individual made a completely arbitrary choice to choose Christ, then it was meaningless. It had no motive. It was just a random, thoughtless act. Of course, every non-Calvinist would say that those who choose Christ certainly have motive for doing so. They want to choose Him, for instance. But as soon as one confesses that this is so, they admit that choices are caused, not uncaused. A choice that is based on a particular motive or reason is a choice that is born out of a causal influence. There were underlying factors that caused the individual to choose the way he did.
There is another ironic implication of the idea that our choices are uncaused. Again, the non-Calvinist will often assert that in order for an individual to legitimately be held responsible for his choices, those choices must be “free.” But just as meaning is grounded in causation, so is responsibility. If an individual's choosing is not necessarily causally related to any character trait or other underlying influence, we cannot legitimately call it “his” choice. A random, purposeless, uncaused act, with no meaning or motive necessarily underlying it, cannot even be called a “choice” of the individual. If a man murders his friend and one were to suggest that his choices were uncaused, we would lose all grounds for accusing the culprit of being responsible for the murder. Yet if we admit that it was his choice, then we further evidence our conviction that the choice was determined by underlying motives, character traits, and/or other factors. It is, in fact, the recognition of underlying motive that causes us to say a criminal is guilty for his actions.
...
Last edited: