You don't need to create a complex atmospheric system to understand that CO2 will trap outgoing heat.
Can I add an addendum to your quote: "and increase the temperature in a closed system".
Since the atmosphere has both sources and sinks and is not necessarily in equilibrium, then it is not for certain that CO2 will increase the temperature. Also, if the carbon system has sources and sinks, then it is not for certain that the CO2 concentrations of the atmosphere are increasing.
In what models does increasing CO2 not trap more heat?
None. But stop introducing these red herrings. The question is not if CO2 traps heat, we are both in agreement that this was established in the 1950s.
What was not established in the 1970s is two things:
1) Is the atmospheric concentration of CO2 increasing or are there carbon sinks which are absorbing the additional carbon (this was first established by Keeley et al., 1976)
2) Is the temperature increasing, or are there certain heat sinks which are nullifying any carbon-induced warming? (this question was answered satisfactorily by Hansen et al., 1981)
Just because lab tests show that CO2 traps heat does not mean the atmosphere behaves like these controlled lab settings. The lab experiments have well controlled and well-understood heat sinks, well-controlled and well-understood measurement methods and no carbon sinks. The labs prove one thing: CO2 traps heat
all else being equal.
And for fear of repeating myself: "
In other words, "all other things being equal", if CO2 increased by X amount, how much would the temperature go up?"
Arrhenius' 1896 paper, for starters.
Recall that Arrhenius had this to say about global warming: "By the influence of the increasing percentage of carbonic acid in the atmosphere, we may hope to enjoy ages with more equable and better climates, especially as regards the colder regions of the earth, ages when the earth will bring forth much more abundant crops than at present, for the benefit of rapidly propagating mankind" (
Arrhenius 1908, pg 63)
I asked for a citation that says we knew there was a "risk". You suggest Arrhenius, who believed the exact opposite. There was no risk, but more benefit!
Let me use an analogy. Let's say you are standing at the top of the Empire State building. You turn your back to the ledge of the building, and then fling a 16 lb bowling ball over your head. The bowling ball hurtles towards the ground and lands on someone's head, killing them instantly.
Could you claim you have no liability for that person's death because you had no idea where the bowling ball would land, and there was no way for you to know that a person would be hit by the bowling ball? Most people would think you were guilty because you unnecessarily risked someone's life, right?
This is a poor analogy because:
1) How objects behave under Earth's gravity is incredibly well understood; the way the climate system responds to heat exchanges is very complex and not as well understood (especially in the 1970s!)
2) The impact of throwing a bowling ball off the Empire State building has almost no conceivable benefits and only the potential to harm; a warmer world could have multiple drawbacks and benefits, both of which are often nebulous and difficult to quantify.
3) There is no concept of gravity sources and sinks in this example. There is no way for the bowling ball to change course, accelerate or decelerate, once being thrown. The addition of CO2 into our atmosphere has various ways of changing course via absorption into carbon sinks; the heat also has a variety of control knobs such as changing cloud cover patterns, ocean absorption, natural orbital changes, changes to solar irradiance, etc.
Here's a better analogy:
Let's say you're throwing darts at a dartboard outside on a windy day. You know how the dart will fly on a windless day (because you've tested it in a lab), but in the wind, it is harder to apply your theory directly because of external effects. Your dartboard has some numbers on it; some are positive and some are negative. But some are covered up as well and it is unknown whether those points are positive or negative. When you throw the dart, you don't know if it is going to land on a positive or negative. Should you be liable if it hits a negative? Is it a serious risk to throw the dart? What if you throw the dart and your "windless dart" theory predicts it will hit the negative but then the wind buffets the dart midflight and it ends up hitting a positive?
There are so many variables, its really hard to figure it out...
The same thing with CO2. We knew that CO2 absorbed heat.
So what? You keep thinking that "CO2 absorbing heat" = "observed man-made global warming with serious negative effects which needs immediate action".
No! CO2 absorbing heat in a controlled lab experiment tells you very little about how the atmosphere-Earth system is going to respond to an influx in CO2. You need more than just "CO2 absorbs heat". You need an understanding of atmospheric circulation, ocean circulation, ocean absorption of heat, ocean absorption of CO2, vegetation sinks, the effects of weathering, changes to solar irradiance, albedo effects of clouds, albedo effects of ice caps, latitudinal variations in heat distribution, effects of orbital variations, observed CO2 increases to validate your theory, observed temperature increases to validate your theory, a solid understanding of heat sources and sinks, a solid understanding of carbon sources and sinks etc.
And after you've done
all that, then you still need to show that a warmer world is bad for humanity. And you still need to show that this requires action because of some risk of negative outcomes.
Very little of this had been accomplished by 1980. Very little.
You can't come back and say that there could be some process that perhaps scrubs CO2 out of the atmosphere. That is like the excuse discussed above, not having any way of knowing that the bowling ball would hit someone.
No, it is not at all like the bowling ball analogy because there were already some possible natural mechanisms for how CO2 could be scrubbed from the atmosphere. Since there were no consistent, longitudinal measurements of how CO2 concentrations were increasing (until Keeley et al., 1976), then it was unclear how important those mechanisms were at scrubbing the CO2 out of the atmosphere. Such natural mechanisms included oceanic absorption, vegetation sinks, weathering, etc.
The bowling ball analogy doesn't work because, once the bowling ball is thrown, there aren't really any plausible natural mechanisms to change the bowling ball's course.
They knew there was a risk.
Remind me who "they" is again? Oil companies in the 1970s? Scientists didn't even know if there was a serious risk!
Let's say the entire house will catch on fire if the temperature goes up another 2 degrees. Could you claim that there are all of these unknown factors, so throwing more wood on the fire poses no risk?
If you calculate that the open window will remove the excess heat from additional logs, then there is no risk.
Imagine an alternate universe where Keeley et al., 1976 found that CO2 concentrations had flat-lined or were dropping after examining the Mauna Loa and South Pole records. Imagine for a moment that this was the case. Now imagine that, based on this observation, scientists needed to explain how this excess CO2 was being scrubbed from the atmosphere and lets say they discovered that a combination of increased vegetation, oceanic absorption and weathering were removing 95% of man-made carbon. Just imagine that for a moment.
Would all those controlled lab experiments that showed that CO2 traps outgoing heat matter?