It has no definite position. It might be found anywhere allowed by the wavefunction it has at that time. (But if no one seeks to find it, it is not actually in any one definite place at a given time.)
I thought I addressed that by stating we observed the electron at times t1 and t2 so we knew it was in locations Q and P. I understand you're leaning on the idea it could be at any or none of the locations specified by the wavefunction, but I can't tell if you've noted the situation I describe (or tried to describe) means there are times when it can't be at Q or P.
The discrete change I refer to is the change from "it can't be at P" to "it can be at P", and this is verified by our observing the electron.
The higher the energy of the photon, the shorter its wavelength, and the more narrowly you can determine the location of the electron you bounce it off. But the higher the energy, the more the photon disturbs the electron's wavefunction.
That didn't really address my question. In short, this is starting to sound like turtles all the way down.
1) Since there are multiple ways of interpreting QM, there is no 'must' about the interpretation. 2) But there can be, by definition, no evidence about what the electron is doing when you aren't measuring it.
Thanks for clarifying per statement 1, and I understand statement 2, hence I added observation to the example.
Some of the bizarre results of QM, like the two slit experiment, suggest that the electron does not take one path, but all possible allowable paths. And is therefore not in one particular place at one time.
I find your use of terms like "path" very curious. It seems rather than saying the electron takes all paths that you're saying it takes no path.
Because the moon is still there even if you aren't looking at it. Even if nobody is looking at it. I do not believe that if everyone stayed inside, and we turned off all our cameras, the tides would disappear. This is not really any different than the assumption that electrons exist between the times when we actively observe them.
Shrug. At least you admit these are assumptions. I guess we can assume anything we want about the things we aren't observing. Would you disagree with that?
I don't see why you think the moon makes your case. What's special about the moon as an object? Why does the moon have a location when I'm not observing it, but the electron doesn't? That seems inconsistent to me. Just because it's easier to detect the location of the moon when I observe it doesn't mean it always has a location when I don't observe it. It seems to me you should answer the same for both.
Now, I realize you were speaking of existence and not location, but in my previous post I tied those 2 together. I was suggesting that in order for a material thing to exist, it must have a location. And so I'm suggesting that the electron always has a location, you just don't know what it is until you observe it. Anything else suggests to me that it ceases to exist for a time (as a particle). Now, if you're suggesting that the wave nature is material, you'll need to explain to me what it is about the wave nature that exists so we can discuss it.
At this point, I'll be up front that we seem to be going in circles. For example, you seem to use the math (wave function) to defend the peculiar observations of QM that defy classical understandings. When I point out further peculiarities, you fall back on classical references to try to dissuade me (the moon). So when I then start speaking in classical terms, you point out how the math of QM interprets those terms differently and we start round the loop again.